Friday, December 30, 2016

Looking back at 2016

Once again, in the spirit of the year-end retrospectives so popular this time of year, I offer up a list of our past year's offerings:

January 25th: "The Second Sex," by Simone de Beauvoir
February 22nd: "An Interest in Life," by Grace Paley
March 28th: Selected Poems by Wislawa Szymborska
April 25th: "Discipline and Punish," by Michel Foucault
May 23rd: "Interpreter of Maladies," by Jhumpa Lahiri
June 27th: "The Prince," by Machiavelli
July 25th: "The Meno," by Plato
August 22nd: "Life of Nicias," by Plutarch
September 26th: "To Perpetual Peace," by Kant
October 24th: "The Chilean Earthquake," by Heinrich von Kleist
November 28th: "Where I Lived, and What I Lived for," by Thoreau.

Here's looking forward to another year of personal growth in 2017, aided and abetted by the mysterious and miraculous power of talking and listening to others.

Friday, November 25, 2016

The U.S. Post Office Loved Henry David Thoreau Unrequitedly

Post Office's 1967 Thoreau stamp
"For my part, I could easily do without the post office. I think that there are very few important communications made through it. To speak critically, I never received more than one or two letters in my life -- I wrote this some years ago -- that were worth the postage."

--"Where I Lived and What I Lived For," from Walden: or Life in the Woods, by Henry David Thoreau, Monday's selection.

Friday, September 23, 2016

Kant's "To Perpetual Peace"

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
The selection this month, "To Perpetual Peace," by Kant, was first published in the year (1795) of the Treaty of Basel, which ended hostilities between France and her combatants of the so-called First Coalition (Prussia, Spain, and Hesse-Kassel).

Historian David A. Bell reflects in his book The First Total War that "To Perpetual Peace" was a product of an era when the so-called "Enlightenment thinkers," including the giant among them Kant, "began to argue that permanent warfare might not, in fact, be the permanent fate of mankind,"

Napoleon Bonaparte was about to bestride the scene in revolutionary France, however, and a new round of wars followed.  More on Monday night...
First edition of "To Perpetual Peace," published in 1795 in Kant's hometown of Königsberg, in Prussia.

Wednesday, August 17, 2016

"Life of Nicias," by Plutarch

"Nicias" by Joachim von Sandrat (1606-1688)
"Life of  Nicias," our selection this month, comes from Plutarch's Lives of the Noble Grecians and Romans. The work is also known as the Parallel Lives, as it contains side-by-side biographies of noteworthy personages of Greco-Roman antiquity, with commentary on the successes and failures of each pair.


Nicias was an Athenian political and military leader of the 5th-century B.C., and the selection relates tales of his penchant for pomp and circumstance, his political rivalries (especially with Alcibiades), and the Athenian military expedition to Sicily, which ended disastrously in 413 B.C.

Bust of Plutarch (ca. 46-ca.119)
in his home village of Chaeronia, Greece
It's a rich narrative, worthy of an epic motion picture.  At its center is the personage of Nicias, the reluctant warrior. He vied with more hawkish elements in Athens's political arena, and negotiated a truce with Sparta and her allies that bears his name.  In Plutarch's telling, is Nicias a hero or anti-hero?

You decide.

Monday, August 15, 2016

"Better Men, Braver and Less Idle": Meno's Paradox

In our meeting on the 25th of last month of Plato's "Meno," what's commonly known as "Meno's Paradox" came up.

As I mentioned in my previous post, the dialogue returns again and again to the question of what virtue is. Here's Meno:

"How will you look for it, Socrates, when you do not know at all what it is? How will you aim to search for something you do not know at all? If you should meet with it, how will you know that this is the thing that you did not know?" (Section 80d in the Grube translation)

The demonstration with the slave boy ensues, in which Socrates proves, and Meno accepts, that a slave boy raised in his household is able to work his way through a geometry problem (with what some consider "leading questions" by Socrates), despite having had no formal training in the discipline.

Socrates concludes that universal truths are embedded in the boy's soul, which he has the ability to "recollect."

"Meno's Paradox" is: if we know something, inquiry is unnecessary, however it we don't know something, inquiry is impossible.  How will we know the truth if we see it?

Socrates reply: "...I would contend at all costs in both word and deed as far as I could that we will be better men, braver and less idle, if we believe that one must search for the things one does not know, rather than if we believe that it is not possible to find out what we do not know and that we must not look for it." (Section 86b).

In other words: Dare to know.

Wednesday, July 27, 2016

Plato's "Meno"

Plato, from Raphael's "School of Athens"
Kudos to the 22 brave souls who made it to the library through intermittent severe thunderstorms on Monday evening for our spirited discussion on Plato's "Meno."

The "Meno" starts off with the title character posing a question as to whether virtue can be taught, is the result of practice, or is inborn.

After a lot of twists and turns -- requests for definitions, attempts at definitions, debates on epistemology (how we come to know), a math demonstration, a section on virtue as knowledge and another contrasting "knowledge" vs. "right opinion" -- a concluding colloquy between Socrates and Meno proceeds as follows (from the Grube translation):

SOCRATES: ...if we were right in the way in which we spoke and investigated in this whole discussion, virtue would be neither an inborn quality nor taught, but comes to those who possess it as a gift from the gods which is not accompanied by understanding, unless there is someone among our statesmen who can make another into a statesman. If there were one, he could be said to be among the living as Homer said Tiresias was among the dead [in Homer's Odyssey], namely, that "he alone retained his wits while the others flitted about like shadows."  In the same manner, such a man would, as far as virtue is concerned, here also be the only true reality compared, as it were, with shadows.
MENO: That is and excellent way to put it, Socrates.
SOCRATES: It follows from this reasoning, Meno, that virtue appears to be present in those of us who may possess it as a gift from the gods. We shall have clear knowledge of this when, before we investigate how it comes to be present in men, we first try to find out what virtue in itself is. But now the time has come for me to go. [Emphasis added].

Socrates then asks Meno to pass his newfound realizations on to Anytus, which will be "for the benefit of the Athenians," as Anytus apparently wields some influence. The dialogue then ends.

 According to R.E. Allen (1), the dialogue "ends in perplexity," and he calls it a piece of "dialectical irony," because Socrates concludes that even though he has asked and probed for a definition of virtue multiple times, these discussants could not produce a suitable answer as to "what virtue in itself is".

However, and this is my additional interpretation, some statesman who have this certain charisma, or "virtue," or "je ne sais quoi," as if as a divine gift, can pass it on to others.  (Witness how our political leaders have performed such feats at the podiums of the Republican and Democratic National Conventions during the past two weeks!)

Thanks to our attendees for grappling with this text, one of the most challenging we've read over the course of the last 12 years.

P.S. Purely coincidentally, our reading last month of the "Prince" had many references to what Machiavelli in Italian called "virtù."  Many thanks to Peter McGullam for noticing this interesting parallel between the readings.  At the risk of sounding a little reductionist, I maintain that Plato's "virtue," like Machiavelli's "virtù," is of the "can do," not "goody-goody" kind.

(1) Allen, R.E., The Dialogues of Plato, vol. 1. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984, p.149.




Friday, June 24, 2016

"Am I politic, am I subtle, am I a Machiavel?'

Santi di Tinto's portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli (1469-1527). 
My title quote is from Shakespeare's "Merry Wives of Windsor."  Once you've noted the Bard's charming use of  "a Machiavel" as a singular personal noun, let the meaning of the adjectives "politic" and "subtle" sink in.

The line encapsulates the basic dilemmas surrounding "The Prince":  Is Niccolò's position statesmanlike or malevolent?  Does he depict affairs as they really are, or as they should be?  Is he at heart a republican or a monarchist?  Is he really "subtle," or is he ruthless?

Questions such as these make this first modern treatise of political philosophy fascinating.  We'll talk more on Monday.


P.S. Note well Niccolò's sixteenth-century political smile in portrait.  Would it fly in the twenty-first century?

Wednesday, April 20, 2016

Unpacking Foucault

Mural of Foucault by Thierry Ehrmann.
Michel Foucault (1926-1984) wrote this month's selection, "the Body of the Condemned," as the first chapter of his book Discipline and Punish: the Birth of the Prison. 

Foucault, who was a member of the prestigious Collège de France, wrote interdisciplinary works on diverse subjects including mental illness, medicine, sexuality, and in this case, the criminal justice system.

"The Body of the Condemned" puts Foucault's technique on display.  He starts with primary historical source materials. The first is an account of the attempted execution by drawing and quartering of Damiens for the failed assassination of King Louis XV in 1757, the second a 19th century day log of rules for "the House of Young Prisoners in Paris."

By the end of the piece, Foucault will have used such historical evidence to make a leap into theory. He asserts that by controlling a man's body, you ultimately control his soul.

Monday, January 25, 2016

de Beauvoir's "The Second Sex"

Simone de Beauvoir in 1967.
Our meeting tonight -- which will take place thanks to all who have helped to dig out the library and surrounding roads after Saturday's massive snowfall -- will be on the Introduction to Simone de Beauvoir's The Second Sex, first published in this country in 1953.

Let me offer the following as a brief intro to the reading.  The Second Sex is a lengthy work, so lengthy it was first published in two volumes (and the French edition, still in print, remains so).

It is a work that incorporates de Beauvoir's insights gleaned from the fields of biology, history, anthropology, sexology, etc. De Beauvoir builds her argument on a scaffolding of French existentialist philosophy.  Here are a few terms you need to know to understand the text in light of this:

en soi: "in itself": an inanimate object is a thing in-itself.  A table, for example, doesn't change.

por soi: "for itself": a human being is "for itself." Unlike a table, it can change, it is a "becoming."

Mitsein: from German, "being with."  Communities of people are a "Mitsein."

Alterity: "Otherness."  It is de Beavoir's basic premise that women are in a state of alterity vis à vis men, and this situation has led to their subordination to men throughout history.